An
example of the limits of vernacular English (at least as Hawking uses it) is
found on page 82: “A star is formed when a large amount of gas (mostly
hydrogen) starts to collapse in on itself due to its gravitational attraction.
… The heat released in this reaction, which is like a controlled hydrogen bomb
explosion, is what makes the star shine.” What “controls” it? It is just an
explosion that lasts millions of years. Hawking is careless with common
language.
The
worst failings are found in the discussions of action near or very near or at a
black hole. Hawking believes that if you fell into one, you would be instantly
destroyed (page 139, but also 89 and 112). Hawking does seem to get it right on
page 87. The fact is that following Einstein’s theory of relativity, and as offered by Hermann
Minkowski (1864-1909) earlier, as you approach the speed of light, time slows
down for you. The astronaut who falls into a black hole might never experience
his own death.
Hawking’s
presentation of the history of astronomy is shallow, with no evidence of
scholarship, insight, or nuance. He leaves out Aristarchos of Samos (?310-230
BCE), Hipparchos of Nikea (190 to 120 BCE), Eratosthenes (276-194 BCE), and Archimedes (?287-212 BCE). He also wrongly
blames Aristotle for every error in ancient science.
1. The
truth is that Aristarchus put the sun at the center of the universe. And he did
that based on knowledge he inherited and built upon. Sir Thomas Heath wrote
several books about the history of mathematics and astronomy. Among them was Aristarchus of Samos, the ancient
Copernicus; a history of Greek astronomy to Aristarchus, together with
Aristarchus's Treatise on the sizes and distances of the sun and moon: a new
Greek text with translation and notes. London: Oxford University Press
(1913). This is not an obscure reference: it has always been available. Other
editions of Aristarchus’s work also were published.
2. Hipparchus of Nicea (190 to 120 BCE) is famous in our time for his measurement of the precession of the equinoxes. The fact that the celestial north pole moves was always a significant problem to ancient astronomers. Precession of the equinoxes was cited by Copernicus as evidence that the Earth moves. Hawking mentions none of that. I understand that he did not want to clutter the book with asides, but presenting a proper history of science is important to this book, especially.
2. Hipparchus of Nicea (190 to 120 BCE) is famous in our time for his measurement of the precession of the equinoxes. The fact that the celestial north pole moves was always a significant problem to ancient astronomers. Precession of the equinoxes was cited by Copernicus as evidence that the Earth moves. Hawking mentions none of that. I understand that he did not want to clutter the book with asides, but presenting a proper history of science is important to this book, especially.
3. Eratosthenes is famous for estimating the diameter of the Earth by measuring shadows on the first day of summer. (The story is a bit more complicated. He might not have done the actual work himself but only ordered it done by scholars working for him at the Great Library of Alexandria. See Circumference by Nicholas Nicastro reviewed here.)
4. If the
Earth goes around the sun, then we ought to be able to measure the parallax,
the apparent shift in position of the stars across the sky, say winter to
summer. Archimedes tried to measure it but failed. He concluded that either the
Earth is at the center, or the universe is unimaginably larger than their
estimates.
The point is that contrary to Hawking’s dismissive claim that the ancient Greeks did not value experiment, Archimedes measured to test a theory. Hipparchus measured. Eratosthenes measured. Ptolemy measured. They did not just spin airy fantasies.
The point is that contrary to Hawking’s dismissive claim that the ancient Greeks did not value experiment, Archimedes measured to test a theory. Hipparchus measured. Eratosthenes measured. Ptolemy measured. They did not just spin airy fantasies.
Hawking
attacks Aristotle several times. And he says that Aristotle placed the Earth at the center of the universe “for mystical reasons.” (page 2)
Aristotle was not a mystic: he had good reasons for putting the Earth at the
center. “The Aristotelian tradition also held that one could work out all the
laws that govern the universe by pure thought: it was not necessary to check by
observation.” (page 15). Despite the many errors we find his works, Aristotle
argued for beginning with observation and experience. His description of the
development of the chick embryo is still considered one of the greatest
experiments in the history of science. Moreover, it was Plato who argued for beginning with ideas (eidos means "form"). Even so, in his dialog “Protagoras”,
Plato has Socrates give clear examples of how empirical knowledge triumphs in a
political debate. Hawking wrongly claims: “Aristotle believed that all the
matter in the universe is made up of four basic elements: earth, air, fire and
water.” (page 16; also 9). In fact, it was Empedocles of Akragas (490-430 BCE)
who posited earth-water-air-fire. Aristotle added a fifth element: aether. (It
became the “quintessence” of alchemy; and we still use “quintessential”
rhetorically.) The ancient theory is not far from our modern ideas about
solids, liquids, gases, and plasma.
(See Aristotle Leads the Way by Joy Hakim, reviewed here.)
(See Aristotle Leads the Way by Joy Hakim, reviewed here.)
As he
opens with attacks on Aristotle, Hawking closes by disparaging Einstein. (He
does acknowledge other contributions, such Einstein’s work on Brownian motion
and the photo-electric effect.) On page 155, Hawking claims that “… Einstein
refused to believe in the reality of quantum mechanics.” That is not true.
Einstein, Schrödinger, and others were not convinced of the “Copenhagen
interpretation” offered by Bohr, Heisenberg, and others. Schrödinger’s cat was
offered as a reductio ad absurdum:
the cat in the box is neither dead nor alive until you lift the lid and look. To Einstein (and other modern physicists) the cat is either alive or dead, regardless of whether or not you look. In other words, Einstein was an objectivist or positivist who believed that reality exists independent of our perceptions: if we all were dead, everything else would still be here, including quantum packet wavicles, whatever they are.
While
Hawking gives full credit to Galileo, he says nothing about the Oxford
calculators of the Merton School (c. 1325-1350). Their work was cited by
Galileo (Two New Sciences, Third Day,
Theorem I, Proposition I: the mean speed theorem). Relative motion was known to
the ancients. Copernicus cited Virgil’s Aeneid
on the appearance of the land moving away from a ship. (See "Copernicus on the Revolution of Heavenly Bodies" reviewed here.)
Among
the many weak analogies, Hawking explains Newton’s theory of gravity: “Thus the
force between two bodies would be twice as strong if one of the bodies (say,
body A) had its mass doubled. This is what you might expect because one could
think for the new body A as being made of two bodies with the original mass.
Each would attract body B with the original force. Thus the total force between
A and B would be twice the original force” (page 16). That is approximately true. Two bodies cannot
occupy the same space at the same time. So, A and A-prime would attract B with
different forces. But Hawking never says “approximately.” He just moves on to
give a poor explanation of why bodies of different weight fall at the same rate
(page 17).
Among
the many internal contradictions based on weak philosophy, are these:
1. Hawking says “… a theory is just a model of the universe, or a restricted part of it, and a set of rules that relate quantities in the model to observations we make. It exists only in our minds and does not have any other reality (whatever that might mean).”
2. But on page 42: “Despite the success of his model and his prediction of Hubble’s observations, Friedmann’s work remained largely unknown in the West until similar models were discovered in 1935 by the American physicist Howard Robertson and the British mathematician Arthur Walker, in response to Hubble’s discovery of the uniform expansion of the universe.” If models were discovered then they can exist independent of our perception of them, like other laws of science, or mathematical truths. They are not arbitrary, existing only in our minds.
3. Hawking equivocates without acknowledging the fundamental problem, or his assumption about it. Near the end (page 167), he says again: “As was explained in Chapter 1, we could never be quite sure that we indeed found the correct theory, since theories can’t be proved.” (See the same also on page 139.)
1. Hawking says “… a theory is just a model of the universe, or a restricted part of it, and a set of rules that relate quantities in the model to observations we make. It exists only in our minds and does not have any other reality (whatever that might mean).”
2. But on page 42: “Despite the success of his model and his prediction of Hubble’s observations, Friedmann’s work remained largely unknown in the West until similar models were discovered in 1935 by the American physicist Howard Robertson and the British mathematician Arthur Walker, in response to Hubble’s discovery of the uniform expansion of the universe.” If models were discovered then they can exist independent of our perception of them, like other laws of science, or mathematical truths. They are not arbitrary, existing only in our minds.
3. Hawking equivocates without acknowledging the fundamental problem, or his assumption about it. Near the end (page 167), he says again: “As was explained in Chapter 1, we could never be quite sure that we indeed found the correct theory, since theories can’t be proved.” (See the same also on page 139.)
4. Hawking
trips over philosophy on page 74: “The success of the unification of the
electromagnetic and weak nuclear forces led to a number of attempts to combine
these two forces with the strong nuclear force into what is called a grand
unified theory (or GUT). This title is rather an exaggeration: the resultant
theories are not all that grand, nor are they fully unified, as they do not
include gravity. Nor are they really complete theories because they contain a
number of parameters whose values cannot be predicted from the theory but have
to be chosen to fit in with experiment.” What he means is that many constants
are determined empirically.
Hawking
has a preference for idealism and rationalism. Important as they are to
epistemology, they are only half of the equation. Hawking prefers that all
constants be derivable by theory, like Planck’s constant. That the
gravitational constant G had to be measured (first by Henry Cavendish in 1798)
is a fact of life. You could just set it equal to 1 and then adjust the meter
and everything else to that. In the 19th century, mu-nought, the magnetic constant, was taken
as 2 and made fundamental to the definition of the ampere, the unit of current.
Today, electricians define the amp from the volt, and then magnetic
permeability from those. The history and utility of dimensionless constants is
beyond the book or this review. But it remains that Hawking is not comfortable
with the empirical discovery of physical constants; and that is an error in his
epistemology.
And it
would seem to be interesting to Hawking and his readers that Maxwell’s
equations can be manipulated to show that the speed of light squared is equal
to the reciprocal of the product of the magnetic constant and the dielectric
constant, but he does not mention it.
Again, he cannot say everything in under 190 pages. That limit, however,
unlike the speed of light, was not written in the stars.
Despite
Hawking’s claim (Chapter 4) that the Newtonian universe is deterministic, it is
well-known (and has been since about 1801) that there are no easy solutions to
a 3-body problem and no synthetic solutions to an N-body problem. In other
words, from Newton’s famous equations, we can approximate well how the Earth
and Moon interact. Add the Sun, and it gets difficult. Predictions about the
relative positions of the eight planets, their moons, and the Sun are
impossible, except by approximations using iterative numerical methods.
Equations alone won’t do it.
Another
example of Hawking’s shortfalls with Newtonian mechanics is found on pages
164-165 when he discusses counterfactual universes. He is attempting to outline
the difficulties in constructing a consistent framework that includes
relativity and quantum mechanics. He says: “There would also be problems with
more than three space dimensions. The gravitational force between two bodies
would decrease more rapidly than it does in three dimensions…. In fact the same
behavior of gravity with distance in more than three space dimensions means that
the sun would not be able to exist in a stable state with pressure balancing
gravity.” In point of fact, it is a truth in Newtonian mechanics that motion in
a conservative field takes place in a plane. Orbits are two dimensional.
Perhaps the problem is that how or why F = G (Mm / r^2) would become some F* = G (Mm / r^3) or … r^1.5 cannot be explained in a book without equations – and that is not so much Hawking’s sin as his publisher’s, though he was complicit in the omission. And, again, with the philosophy: the sun is not “stable.” Whether some counterfactual physical laws could describe a sun with a longer or shorter life, the fact is that the sun is a process.
Perhaps the problem is that how or why F = G (Mm / r^2) would become some F* = G (Mm / r^3) or … r^1.5 cannot be explained in a book without equations – and that is not so much Hawking’s sin as his publisher’s, though he was complicit in the omission. And, again, with the philosophy: the sun is not “stable.” Whether some counterfactual physical laws could describe a sun with a longer or shorter life, the fact is that the sun is a process.
Long,
long ago, I sang an ABC song for my daughter:
“These are the rules of astronomy.
We’re beset by entropy.
Things run down
And things burn out.
This I know without a doubt.
O B A F G K M.
Then they start all over again.”
Discussing
the electromagnetic force (page 70) Hawking says: “A large body, such as the
earth or sun, contains nearly equal numbers of positive and negative charges.
Thus the attractive and repulsive forces between individual particles nearly
cancel each other out, and there is very little net electromagnetic force.” OK…
what about the fact that the Sun and the Earth both have magnetic fields,
though Mars and the Moon do not? I realize that he cannot discuss everything in
182 pages, but neither would it have hurt to have said a little more to the
millions of us who do know some science.
Hawking’s
explanation of the diffraction slit paradox ignores the essence in the problem.
He also assumes no common experience with waves. “That is to say, the crests of
one set of waves may coincide with the troughs of the other set. The two sets
of waves then cancel each other out, rather than adding up to a stronger wave
as one might expect.” (page 57-58) Why would you expect that? In fact, he
illustrates both cases on page 57. He goes back and forth calling electrons
waves and particles, and that’s fine. But with the diffraction grate
experiment, what happens if you try it with baseballs rather than photons (or
electrons)?
His
drawing on page 22 leads to the apparent conclusion that the farther you are
from something, the faster light travels.
The explanation of arbitrary
coordinate systems (page 23) offers a poor example of polar coordinates. When
the Pythagorean theorem is applied to the illustration on page 25 the distance
from the sun to Alpha Centauri comes out in years-miles, as if you could mix
apples and oranges. The drawing on page 31 is greatly exaggerated without
explanation. If starlight were bent so much by the sun’s gravity, that fact
would have been obvious to the Babylonians.
Figure
5.2 on page 73 is labeled “A proton and an antiproton collide at high energy,
producing a couple of almost free quarks.” Actually, the picture could be
anything in a cloud chamber. It reminded me of the article in the Journal of Irreproducible Results on how
to save money in research by using the same illustration, but changing the
caption. What is an “almost free quark”? Did it come into existence almost
without the exchange of energy? Are these “almost free quarks” almost bound
together as almost-electrons? He never says.
Toward
the close, discussing “The Arrow of Time” (Chapter 9). Hawking offers this: “Suppose
the pieces of the jigsaw start off in a box in an ordered arrangement in which
they form a picture. If you shake the box, the pieces will take up another arrangement.
This will probably be a disordered arrangement in which the pieces don’t form a
picture. … but the more you shake the box… the pieces will be in a completely
jumbled state…” (page 146). True
enough. But it is well known to
mathematicians that if you want to pack marbles in the box efficiently, you can
pour them in as a heap, and then shake the box to recursively find the optimal arrangement.
The
bottom line is that this brief book full of golly and gee-whiz fails on close inspection.
PREVIOUSLY ON
NECESSARY FACTS
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.